Search This Blog

Showing posts with label Naturalistic Philosophers. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Naturalistic Philosophers. Show all posts

Wednesday, 6 May 2015

David Hume for Novice Philosophers. Part II: Religionism in The Academy, Sceptical Limits on Naturalistic Empiricism, and Backgammon

Hume

At the beginning of his academic career, Hume spent time debating Jesuits of the college of La Flèche, where he spent much of his savings during the 4 years there writing “A Treatise of Human Nature”. This marked the beginning of Hume's career of undermining religious thought and belief. Hume is understood to have been opposed to religious enthusiasm, but otherwise often taken to be a believer. 

However, he was later in his career defended against charges of heresy by claims that, as an atheist, Church law did not apply to him. Moreover, his scepticism clearly targets any claims that a god being could be known in any other way than by repeated sense based experience, such that ontological arguments for the existence of a god relying upon a-priori concepts and reasoning cannot stand.

In contrast to Hume's scepticism about certainty about objects of faith, the other two famous Empiricist philosophers were Hume's predecessor John Locke, and his contemporary Bishop George Berkeley, both of whom were also Christians and theologians - particularly Berkeley. This gives one a sound impression of the ongoing strength of representation of Judeo Christian religion in the academy and academic institutions of the time. Hume was all but surrounded by clerics and devouts who thought that the character of God in the Christian Bible represented a real being, and whose peers and allies would tend to aggressively undermine any alternative narratives and commentaries as explanations of life and human existence, and with no real regard for strength of argument or reason.

Berkeley's Empiricism was also underpinned by scepticism. However, Berkeley's scepticism about the reliability of the senses was even stronger than that of Descartes. It led him to Idealism, according to which ideas and the mind are all that exists, and according to which there is in fact no external world at all outside of the mind. All of existence was in fact an idea in the mind of the Biblical character of God - whom Berkeley believed to be a real supernatural entity. (It is not difficult to trace Descartes commitment to the existence of an external world as the creation of the god being that he also believed to exist, since his brain-mind dualism is based upon a metaphysical dualism that regards mind as constituted of real 'spooky mind stuff' that is not the same as the real material stuff that the body is made of.)

Berkeley
Berkeley and Hume were both interested in John Locke's dictum that ideas are representations of objects that cause them via either sense or internal reflection, but that there is no way to know that the objects exist: only the representing ideas. So as with Hume after him, Locke assumes the existence of the external mind-independent world, but recognises that ideas are what is apparent to the mind, and that the mind cannot get past the representing idea to the actual object.
Locke


Unlike Hume and Locke, Berkeley bites the bullet on the inability of the mind to directly perceive any external object, and simply asserts that such things don't really exist apart from perceptions/ideas of persons and in the mind of the Biblical God character whom he believed to be real. (It is somewhat of a puzzle how it can be the case even for Berkeley that the god being he believed existed would not have to be an external entity and not an idea in Berkeley's own mind, but that is another matter). This leads him to his principle of Idealism - esse est percipi: existence is perception or to be is to be perceived. This involves a much stronger scepticism about the senses and their role in knowledge production than that of even Descartes who simply doubts the ability of the senses to provide reliable information and thence knowledge.

Hume rejects Berkeley as effectively solipsistic, and regards that experience is of some external reality, and does not see the entire concept of experience and sense experience as meaningful otherwise. A keystone of both Descartes, Locke, and Berkeley's view is the impression and idea of the reality of the self, and Hume attacks any certainty about this concept outright as circular in A Treatise:
“If any impression gives rise to the idea of a self, that impression must continue invariably the same through the whole course of our lives, since the self is supposed to exist in that manner. But there is no impression constant and invariable. Pain and pleasure, grief and joy, passions and sensations succeed each other and never all exist at the same time. It cannot therefore be from any of these impressions or from any other that the idea of the self is derived, and,consequently there is no such idea. (
A Treatise of Human Nature, 164. https://www.gutenberg.org/files/4705/4705-h/4705-h.htm)
More devastatingly, as indicated in parentheses two paragraphs above, Hume points out that there does not seem to be any way that Berkeley can claim that the god being whose mind is supposed to sustain all of existence is not in fact just an idea in Berkeley's mind. A vicious circularity in both explanatory, conceptual, and metaphysical terms arises, which circularity is arguably simply not recoverable for Berkeley.

However, Hume's scepticism as expressed in both the problem of induction and the inability to truly know the real fact of the matter in causal relations was strong enough to cause his empiricist conclusions serious difficulty. He can't get past his simple and complex sense impressions to causal relations or to external objects either. He has dispensed with a-priori reasoning for the task, and has only probable knowledge based upon regular experiences, which cannot present the detailed nature of causal relations or give the mind access to external objects except by assumption that there is an external nature to be experienced and that the information intuitively associated with it could not come from anywhere else. Any real regularities in nature - and perhaps nature itself - have to remain the consequence of an intuitive assumption supported by and about repetitive experiences. This overpowering of even synthetic a-posteriori reason by his scepticism di not dislodge Hume's naturalism, but did lead Hume to openly brood darkly:
The intense view of these manifold contradictions and imperfections in human reason has so wrought upon me, and heated my brain, that I am ready to reject all belief and reasoning, and can look upon no opinion even as more probable or likely than another. Where am I, or what? From what causes do I derive my existence, and to what condition shall I return? Whose favour shall I court, and whose anger must I dread? What beings surround me? and on whom have, I any influence, or who have any influence on me? I am confounded with all these questions, and begin to fancy myself in the most deplorable condition imaginable, inviron'd with the deepest darkness, and utterly depriv'd of the use of every member and faculty. (Treatise 1.4.7.8)
Hume's response is to distract himself with living, eating, and playing backgammon so that the darkness fades. (Treatise 1.4.7.9)

In his attacks on the doctrines of Descartes and Berkeley, Hume takes some care not to bruise theological and general religious sensibilities too openly, although as we will see in part III not so carefully as to avoid expulsion and lifetime exclusion from the academy as a working and tenured philosopher. He clearly places empirical detection of entities as a necessary condition for existence claims:
The existence, therefore, of any being can only be proved by arguments from its cause or its effect; and these arguments are founded entirely on experience. If we reasonĂ  priori, any thing may appear able to produce any thing. The falling of a pebble may, for ought we know, extinguish the sun; or the wish of a man controul the planets in their orbits. It is only experience, which teaches us the nature and bounds of cause and effect, and enables us to infer the existence of one object from that of another035. Such is the foundation of moral reasoning, which forms the greater part of human knowledge, and is the source of all human action and behaviour. (Hume, D. Enquiry Section XII Part 3, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 12.29)


Hume's rejection of Descartes' certainty about self and about the existence of the Christian god character as real, his rejection of Berkeley's idealism, and his emphasis on the impossibility of knowing about anything except for a-posteriori synthetically on an empirical basis: these were probably enough to see his end as an endorsed philosopher in the academy. However, as has been alluded to already, Hume launched a concerted philosophical attack on human testimony - especially religiously inspired testimony, which is of course the stuff of religious texts.




In An Enquiry, after delivering four arguments that human testimony about miracles must be regarded as unreliable, he concludes:

The plain consequence is (and it is a general maxim worthy of our attention), “That no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle, unless the testimony be of such a kind, that its falsehood would be more miraculous, than the fact, which it endeavours to establish: And even in that case there is a mutual destruction of arguments, and the superior only gives us an assurance suitable to that degree of force, which remains, after deducting the inferior.” (Hume, D. An Enquiry Concering Human Understanding Section XII Part 3, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 12.29)

In short, not only does Hume’s empiricism say that even if there was really a god of kind claimed in Judeo-Christian texts it would be impossible to have any knowledge about them as a fact on a probable basis (the only available basis) since they are unavailable to experience, but human testimony about miracles or supernatural intervention is dramatically less reliable than empirical observation of nature. In fact it is wholly unreliable where the falsity of the testimony would be more surprising than the miracle claimed on an empirical basis.

The intention is that since all miracles are more miraculous than the prospective falsehood of their testimonies, the testimonies are probably false. In other words, if using reason related to our empirical knowledge of how flawed the testimony of human beings is, the miracle testified to is less surprising than the falsehood of the testimony would be, then reject the testimony. In still other words: reject testimony all the time if it is about a miracle that requires us to override knowledge based upon our empirical experience of nature - even if that is only probable in nature.

Put yet another way: we can know facts of the world and nature as probably the case only, and testimony that contravenes or contradicts that empirical knowledge - claiming miracles for example - is unlikely to be true since it is less probable by dint of empirical understanding of the reliability of human testimony about unlikely events. This is, of course, applicable to entire religious texts that are taken to be miraculous and supernaturally inspired.

A direct consequence of Hume’s skeptical empiricism is that you couldn’t know anything about any kind of supernatural god by testimony, and you can’t rely on any written or spoken reports of miracles. Theses are not happy outcomes for theists and Hume’s theological sparring partners. As we will see – they preferred to torpedo his career rather than deal with the arguments.

Tuesday, 5 May 2015

David Hume for Novice Philosophers. Part I: Sceptical Empiricist and Philosophical Naturalist

David Hume



Bruce R Long B App Sc. (Computing), BA Hons 1 (Philosophy), MPhil (Eng.) PhD candidate (Analytic Philosophy) 

Although one of the most renowned of the British empiricist philosophers, David Hume is best known for his scepticism, the metaphysical and epistemic implications of which have been debated by philosophers since Kant (who opposed Hume's metaphysics and moral theories strenuously on behalf of Protestant patrons and their theist doctrine). The best and most famous example of Hume's scepticism is his view of causality.

Hume asserted that we could never be certain that a particular kind of physical effect would always follow from the same kind of physical cause. The next time you drop something, gravity might behave anomalously and the object might go sideways. This is referred to as the problem of induction:
But to convince us, that all the laws of nature, and all the operations of bodies without exception, are known only by experience, the following reflections may, perhaps, suffice. Were any object presented to us, and were we required to pronounce concerning the effect, which will result from it, without consulting past observation; after what manner, I beseech you, must the mind proceed in this operation? It must invent or imagine some event, which it ascribes to the object as its effect; and it is plain that this invention must be entirely arbitrary. The mind can never possibly find the effect in the supposed cause, by the most accurate scrutiny and examination. For the effect is totally different from the cause, and consequently can never be discovered in it. Motion in the second Billiard-ball is a quite distinct event from motion in the first; nor is there any thing in the one to suggest the smallest hint of the other. A stone or piece of metal raised into the air, and left without any support, immediately falls: But to consider the matter a priori, is there any thing we discover in this situation, which can beget the idea of a downward, rather than an upward, or any other motion, in the stone or metal?(Hume, D. Enquiry,  Section IV, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E4.9 )

One could be forgiven for thinking that this means that Hume was a sceptic about nature and natural laws themselves as real, and therefore sceptical about the basis of science in natural lawful nomic (law like or invariant) constraints. However, his scepticism is about our own epistemic access to nature: what we can possibly know about it with certainty. Hume's experiential data-gathering empiricism is exemplified clearly in the above passage in the first and second sentences. He thought empirical data was the only way of knowing anything (any matters of fact, or contingent facts in the world) reliably. However, Hume's scepticism about our ability to really know what is going on in nature and in causality troubles this empiricist view:
If we would satisfy ourselves, therefore, concerning the nature of that evidence, which assures us of matters of fact, we must enquire how we arrive at the knowledge of cause and effect. I shall venture to affirm, as a general proposition, which admits of no exception, that the knowledge of this relation is not, in any instance, attained by reasonings a priori; but arises entirely from experience, when we find, that any particular objects are constantly conjoined with each other. Let an object be presented to a man of ever so strong natural reason and abilities; if that object be entirely new to him, he will not be able, by the most accurate examination of its sensible qualities, to discover any of its causes or effects.(Hume, D. Enquiry Section IV, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 4.6, Emphasis Added)

I suggest that to regard Hume as a sceptic about science and nature rather than an empiricist first would be a misapprehension. However, as we will see later in this post and in Part II, Hume’s scepticism presents some difficult problems for his naturalism, and for realism about the external natural world (where external means existing outside of and apart from the mind and thought). For now, however, we can observe that, in all of his other philosophical musings, Hume tended to either emphasise or else openly rely upon the explanatory the role of nature (via empirical internal or mental experience), and to openly eschew supernaturalism and supernaturalist testimony (belief in the existence of supernatural entities and the ability to know any such thing) as constituting any kind of explanatory option.

Nature and Hume


The term ‘nature’ was at the time of Hume’s writings a philosophical term of art, and its real meaning and correct definition have been debated by philosophers from Aristotle to John Stuart Mill (who famously attempted a disambiguation and lamented the difficulties associated with its use in his 1874 ‘On Nature’). This is especially with respect to conceptions of human nature. 

In Hume’s moral theory - which has come to be known as moral sentimentalism because of the central role of human sentiment as a basis for moral values - common moral sentiments are determined in part by internal psychological similarities between human agents (although the term 'psychological' is anachronistic to his career and work). These psychological similarities are rooted in both human nature, nature in a broader sense, and in shared culture. It is precisely for these reasons, and because of Hume's rejection of the role of anything supernatural, that Hume’s theory of moral sentiments is an ethical naturalist theory 3.

In Chapter 10 of his famous 'Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding'  (titled 'Of Miracles'), Hume elevates natural material evidence in conjunction with careful step by step consideration of empirical information above human testimony, regarding the latter as all but useless in comparison as a basis for reliable knowledge. This applies especially where a testimony claimed supernatural/miraculous, or highly unusual events that would be remarkable by natural standards.

What Hume rejected, along with certain a priori knowledge about things such as cause and effect and the reliability of testimony of miracles, was the kind of a priori certainty that Rene Descartes sought to identify in his cogito. The Cogito is the name for Descartes’most famous idea – I think therefore I am/exist (which he never in fact stated in so many words). It is the idea that the only thing a person can know with certainty is that their thoughts exist. Descartes matched this posit with the idea that the Biblical God character (whom he thought actually existed) inspired and sustained a priori knowledge as well as sustaining mathematical truths. The foundation of all of these conclusions was Descartes' doctrine or principle of clear and distinct ideas: that if one could conceive of something as a clear and distinct idea, then that thing must be real. This is a form of a priori reasoning, or reasoning that does not require any experience of external (not mind or language dependent) past events and outcomes.

Recall that Hume rejected the value of a-priori reasoning pertaining to knowledge of facts about the world, and he emphasised the role of contradiction:

That there are no demonstrative arguments in the case, seems evident; since it implies no contradiction, that the course of nature may change, and that an object, seemingly like those which we have experienced, may be attended with different or contrary effects. May I not clearly and distinctly conceive, that a body, falling from the clouds, and which, in all other respects, resembles snow, has yet the taste of salt or feeling of fire? Is there any more intelligible proposition than to affirm, that all the trees will flourish in December and January, and decay in May and June? Now whatever is intelligible, and can be distinctly conceived, implies no contradiction, and can never be proved false by any demonstrative argument or abstract reasoning a-priori(Hume, D. Enquiry Section IV, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 4.18. Emphasis added.)
The term ‘demonstrative arguments’ in this passage refers to arguments from what does normally happen contingently in the world, rather than what somehow should happen according to a-priori reasoning just in our heads without any recording of outside events. Hume is being sceptical about our ability to be certain about natural laws, including constancy of cause and effect. He is saying that just because we have seen a certain outcome n times does not mean that we can be assured that the outcome will occur again the same way at the n+1 occurrence. This is even if it seems to be governed by natural lawful constraints and has always been totally consistent in the past. There is no demonstrative argument available that will prove the certainty of the outcome next time: no argument from reference to all or any of the past examples of a similar system, event, or situation.

In the above quotation, Hume intends his scepticism and empiricism to turn Descartes' conception of clear and distinct ideas - the foundation of The Cogito - against the conclusion that it is supposed to support. Descartes doubted everything about human perception and science, but not the certainty of awareness of and existence of one’s thoughts, which he took to be undeniably real for certain because of the intervention of a god being. Hume dispenses with even that certainty because of his sceptical empiricism, and with it the ability to know the god being if it exists. Overall, what Hume has to rely upon is a probable knowledge only. That is to say, we can know only that something is probable by empirical means:
 If we be, therefore, engaged by arguments to put trust in past experience, and make it the standard of our future judgment, these arguments must be probable only, or such as regard matter of fact and real existence, according to the division above mentioned. But that there is no argument of this kind, must appear, if our explication of that species of reasoning be admitted as solid and satisfactory. We have said, that all arguments concerning existence are founded on the relation of cause and effect; that our knowledge of that relation is derived entirely from experience; and that all our experimental conclusions proceed upon the supposition, that the future will be conformable to the past.  (Hume, D. Enquiry Section IV, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 4:19. Emphasis added.)
That supposition is, as I have described above, something that Hume asserts we must be sceptical about due to our ignorance. We don’t have a clue what really joins a cause to its effect, says Hume: we only know that one always comes after the other in proximity to it. For Hume, knowing things are probably the case or probably a fact is as good as it gets. His doubts about the reliability of the senses as a basis for gaining information from nature empirically (by past experience including repeated experiment) are not nearly as strict as those of Descartes, and his empiricism puts him at odds with Descartes about the value of empirically based science for gaining knowledge. Yet he rejects Descartes a-priori as unreliable, and and along with that Descartes’ Cogito becomes as only probable knowledge, and not certain:

It is only after a long course of uniform experiments in any kind, that we attain a firm reliance and security with regard to a particular event. Now where is that process of reasoning, which, from one instance, draws a conclusion, so different from that which it infers from a hundred instances, that are nowise different from that single one? This question I propose as much for the sake of information, as with an intention of raising difficulties. I cannot find, I cannot imagine any such reasoning. But I keep my mind still open to instruction, if any one will vouchsafe to bestow it on me.(Hume, D. Enquiry Section IV, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 4:20. Emphasis added.)

Hume relies on the regularity available through empirical observation, but only as probably predictive about future events. Hume's sceptical doctrine of causality is often taken to be not only about epistemic access - or our inability to get enough information about what will happen in a particular kind of system to predict what it will do in the future - but about actual unpredictability in physical systems. However, arguably, Hume's bite-the-bullet approach to causality - which saw him assert scepticism about empirical certainty in the constant regularity of causes and their effects - is not intended to undermine his empiricism.

Thus Hume is a sceptic and an empiricist. However, Hume’s scepticism causes him what is arguably a significant problem for his empiricism.

Rene Descartes
How, then, is empiricism and Hume's version of naturalistic scientism (a term anachronistic to Hume) prevail in the face of his scepticism about cause and effect, and his general scepticism? His empiricism relies on probable knowledge from experiment, which is far closer to scientific methodology and reasoning than is Descartes’Cogito.


As I have mentioned above, Hume rejects the thoroughgoing scepticism about the reliability of the senses that causes Descartes to reject experimental and materialist science as ineffectual. Descartes rejects the senses as reliable, and favours a-priori thought as the only way to know, and to know the god of the Bible, which character he took to exist. Descartes elevates a-priori reasoning - including that based upon mathematics and logic - as perfect and god-inspired. Materialist science, however, he regards as completely undermined by necessary doubts about the reliability of human senses as a way of knowing what is real in the world. According to Hume, however, sense impressions (which are in fact a complicated internal conception of the senses due to Hume’s scepticism) of empirical experiences are exactly where probable synthetic knowledge - the only kind available - must originate.
Descartes

Descartes was a devout theist and theologian, and when he referred to God he was making a reference in religious faith. Hume's numerous references to ‘God’, on the other hand, are famously deistic (he appoints no specific theological character to, nor claims a belief in the existence of any god being) and arguably tongue in cheek or else calculated to endorse critical thinking on the matter of how knowledge of the divine might be sustained. That or they are far more ambiguous in terms of ontological and doxastic (belief) commitments. Such references are arguably also fashioned after his unambiguous critical rejection of both religious enthusiasm and religious testimony.

Importantly, Hume intends his scepticism and empiricism to turn Descartes' conception of clear and distinct ideas - the foundation of The Cogito - against the conclusion that it is supposed to support: God exists because he can be conceived of as a clear and distinct idea and is therefore real. According to Hume, one can’t rely on human testimony about alleged miracles, and if there is any kind of god, you couldn’t possibly know such a being existed a-priori (and thus by faith).
 Whatever is may not be. No negation of a fact can involve a contradiction. The non-existence of any being, without exception, is as clear and distinct an idea as its existence...That the cube root of 64 is equal to the half of 10, is a false proposition, and can never be distinctly conceived. But that Caesar, or the angel Gabriel, or any being never existed, may be a false proposition, but still is perfectly conceivable, and implies no contradiction. (Hume, D. Enquiry Section XII Part 3, http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html, E 12.28)

This is the basis of what philosophers refer to as Hume's Fork. Hume regarded that there are two kinds of knowing: knowledge of the relations of ideas in a-priori reasoning, and knowledge of external mind-independent matters of fact in the world. The first kind of knowledge - a-priori analytic knowledge, is demonstrated in the above passage. It involves the identification of true and false statements on the basis of the presence or absence of contradiction: on a logical basis. The second kind of knowledge (see earlier quoted passage E 4:18 above) - called synthetic a-posteriori - requires experience of patterns and regularities in nature or in the external world.  

According to Cartesian a priori reasoning and the principle of clear and distinct ideas: it is every bit as likely that there is not any god being as that there is one. According to Hume there is no knowledge to be had in this - only in what has been empirically experienced through the senses - or more precisely - sense impressions.

It is these kinds of claims that were regarded as broadly heretical by the theologians of the time, and the same theologians and their allies troubled Hume’s career thereafter. In Part II we will explore the impact of Hume's scepticism on his naturalism and his theory of mind (there are serious problems for the senses and the existence of the external world), and the damage done to him by the religionist academy. 

1. Descartes, R. Meditations on First Philosophy, translated by John Cottingham, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996.

 ( See also The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch and Anthony Kenny, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3 vols. 1984-1991.)

2. Hume, D. An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, edited by Tom L. Beauchamp, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 1999. (See also <http://www.davidhume.org/texts/ehu.html>)

3. Hume, D. An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, edited by Tom L. Beauchamp, Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 1998.

4. Hume, D. Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford, 1978), ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H. Nidditch.

5. Mill, J. S., Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, J. M. Robson (ed.), Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1963ff.

Saturday, 21 March 2015

Charles Sanders Peirce: Introduction to a tragic genius.

Charles Sanders Peirce
Bruce R Long B App Sc. (Computing), BA Hons 1 (Philosophy), MPhil (Eng.) PhD candidate (Analytic Philosophy)

Charles Sanders Peirce is known to philosophers as the first serious proponent of scientific and philosophical pragmatism. A trained and capable chemist and polymath who made significant contributions to mathematics and astronomy, Peirce saw his true calling as being that of a logician and philosopher of science. He made groundbreaking and influential contributions to the field of formal logic - which Peirce saw as a conceptual and practical extension of the semiotics, or science of signs, that he himself largely founded.

Among other significant contributions to mathematics and the sciences, Peirce suggested a cardinal arithmetic for infinite numbers well before Georg Cantor's set theoretic contribution, and predicted the use of electrical switching circuits for logic as early as 1887 - well before any developments in the field of computing and the pioneering work of Von Neumann and Claude Elwood Shannon (father of mathematical communication theory and pioneer in transistor logic).

Peirce taught untenured for a time in prestigious settings of Johns Hopkins University - which was to be his last posting due to comprehensive sabotage of his career by his enemies. He had other roles as diverse as calculator for The United States Coast and Geodetic Survey to astronomer for the American Academy of Sciences, and in later life as a consulting engineer and a contributor to American philosophy journal The Monist. 

Peirce's Early Pragmatism, and later 'Pramaticism'


A statement of Peirce's early pragmatism is not difficult, and Peirce's own early definition is perhaps the best to rely upon here:

"Consider what effects, which might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then the whole of our conception of those effects is the whole of our conception of the object. (Peirce 1878/1992, p. 132)"
The focus on outcomes and abstraction of causal pathways is a mainstay of a lot of pragmatism, but Peirce's focus is on obtaining materially satisfying and verifiable results. An upshot is that, using Peircian scientific pragmatism as a larger scientific philosophy and methodology, one does not commit to believing something a fact without material experimental evidence, and one chooses the least expensive experiment to achieve the minimal results required. A more expensive experiment that gives more accurate results is a practical waste of effort if the lesser results are adequate.

Peirce famously ascribes the intellectual heritage of his thought about pragmatism to Kant's normative approach to metaphysics (the study of what exists and how) and epistemology (the study of what knowledge is and how we get it), but the above statement of pragmatism owes more to theist, theologian, and philosopher Rene Descartes' conception of clear and distinct ideas.

Descartes' concept underlies the famous 'Cogito', which is restated by philosophers as 'cogito ergo sum', or, 'I think therefore I am', according to which the only thing the existence of which one can be truly certain about is one's own mind, as evidenced by one's own thought. For rationalist Descartes, materialistic science was epistemically unreliable (an odd idea for a professional lens grinder, which was largely theologically motivated) but a-priori mathematical and logical concepts were underwritten by the Christian biblical god character as all but infallible. Correspondingly, on an a-priori basis - his thesis/principle of clear and distinct ideas implies that if one can conceive of something clearly and express this in some formal or at least systematic sense, then that which is conceived of is not only possible but real.

Peirce is better described as a deist than a Cartesian style theist or a theist in the more traditional Christian sense, as his conception of god - formulated against the backdrop of the American ideal of manifest destiny and constitutional freedom of religious belief, is significantly incompatible with important tenets of Judeo-Christian theology (Sims, 2008). Peirce's pragmatism incorporates the Cartesian clear and distinct ideas doctrine as only one of three elements, which he expresses in terms of three 'grades of clarity'. Apart from this however, Peirce opposed Cartesian philosophy and philosophy of science as almost comprehensively both inadequate and wrong (Peirce, 1886).

Descartes' rationalist principle of clear and distinct ideas largely comprises the the first grade of clarity, which is attained when one has a clear practical but unreflective and in fact empirical grasp of it. That is to say, everyday empirical experience (for empiricism in general terms is about familiarity with something due to previous experiential encounters or previously experientially accrued information) provides a basis for an unanalysed, unreflective basic grasp of a concept, and this constitutes the first grade of clarity. Note, however, that Descartes' conception of a clear and distinct idea does not require the empirical element but can be completely a-priori (armchair pondering).

The second grade of clarity is special to Peirce. It demonstrates his pursuit of a scientistic, if not scientific, pragmatism, and exemplifies Peirce's idea of himself as a philosopher of science and scientific method. The second grade is attained when one can articulate a general scientifically coherent definition of the concept. The final and perhaps most obviously pragmatic grade of clarity is attained when one can practically apply one's understanding per the first two grades in material application or tasks (Atkin, IEP).

For example, the basic idea of tactile sense perception inherited from the experience of others and one's personal experience of tactile sensory stimuli constitutes a first grade of clarity about tactile sense perception. The ability to define this in terms of the action of the peripheral and central nervous systems and the function thereof would exemplify the second grade of clarity. Finally, such things as the ability to perform surgery to repair nerve damage and the testing of a patient's response to tactile stimuli to diagnose pathologies, as based upon the first two grades, are example of the third grade.

Later in his career Peirce became dissatisfied with both his own earlier conception of pragmatism and that of his intellectual heirs and peers Dewey and James. James' formulation favours a subjective and partly more Cartesian approach to pragmatism, which was unpalatable to Peirce, whose rejection of the a-priori in favour of repeatable scientific experiment and practical proof in terms of measurable effects was a keystone of his pragmatism. Importantly, this meant that Peirce's conception of pragmatism incorporated a notion of what contemporary logicians refer to as soundness: that propositions are only meaningful if there is a demonstrable referent or correspondent for them in the material world.

An upshot of Peirce's original formulation is that an untested diamond could be said to be hard or soft in the absence of material/physical experimental data. In Peirce's later formulation, which regarded certain kinds of law-like or nomic possibilities as real and material, this outcome is removed. Peirce regarded the earlier formulation as a crude 'nominalism', by which he meant not that it was simply about labeling or naming properties, but that according to it the governing laws of physics were not taken to be real and to have a measurable and real predictive influence on the estimation of physical outcomes and belief commitment to facts pre-experimentation (Peirce, 1998).

In formal terms, Peirce's later formulation of pragmatism in terms of logic incorporating scientific methodology and the philosophy of science embraced a realist modalism: possibilities underwritten by experimentally proven physical laws are taken to be real.

Peirce and James, James and Clifford


It is Atkin that has perhaps best succinctly described the contrast between the 'pragmaticism' of Peirce and the pragmatism of his colleague and later rival William James:

"Firstly, Peirce and James have different ideas about the philosophical uses to which a pragmatic method should be put. James is famously anti-intellectualist in his philosophy, distrusting the extent to which we can answer all the important human questions with a materialistic and scientific approach to understanding the universe and our place in it. Peirce, on the other hand, particular in his later work, sees the whole of philosophy embedded within a scientific system and the pragmatic maxim centrally embedded in philosophy. The consequence is that James tends to see pragmatism, and his philosophy, as the stepping off point where materialist and purely intellectualist sciences fail to answer our questions about which beliefs are justifiable. Religious and moral questions require a separate criterion of justification, and this is where a pragmatic method determines what difference I take some such belief to have, and why it is reasonable to hold that belief.
For Peirce, philosophy in general, and the pragmatic maxim in particular, should never stray this far from scientific inquiry. The important philosophical questions, and those with which the pragmatic maxim are concerned, remain firmly within the realm of scientific and intellectualist inquiry. As far as Peirce is concerned, the questions to which James is inclined to apply a pragmatic method are largely beyond the realm of fruitful philosophical inquiry. For Peirce pragmatism is strictly within the realms of scientific sensibilities: for James, it begins at the point where our scientific explanations fall short." (2008, Atkin)
There are larger differences between the overall philosophies of James and Peirce, and in particular Atkin notes that:

 "The primary difference between Peirce and James is that the pragmatic maxim in Peirce’s work is a theory of meaning, but in the hands of James, it becomes a theory of truth. This, however, is due to more crucial differences between the two that mean James’ notion of pragmatism far outstretches a simple meaning criterion, and reflects his more fundamental thoughts about philosophy in general." (2008, Atkin)
James was a theist in a more traditional sense than Peirce, and this can often be seen as a motivation in James' philosophy - especially in his propensity to preserve the panpsychical idea that mind does not require to be the upshot of, or existentially dependent upon, evolutionary processes and an evolved brain-bearing organism (since presumably otherwise it is hard for God to have a mind.) With respect to pragmatism, James was happy to ascribe truth value to a-priori subjective propositions in such as way as belief systems were internally consistent. In brute terms: one should believe what works in one's subjective doxastic context, on a law like basis for consistency. Peirce rejected this. James had a near parallel argument with realist non-theist and non-believer William Kingdon Clifford, who required that belief without material evidence was nonsense and unreliable (Blackburn, 2004, locn 378-423).

James was a publiciser of pragmatism, and credited Peirce with its development. However, Peirce was aware that James highly influential formulation of pragmatism was at odds with his own. Teh argumetn between Peirce and James about the correct definition of scientific pragmatism or pragmatism in the context of scientific methodology and philosophy foreshadowed many of the debates that still take place between materialist reductionists and liberal naturalists, non-reductionists and anti-physcialists.


William James

A Case Study in Cowardly, Infantile, Career Sabotage


Peirce's life is a sad object lesson in human nature and the nature of the American upper class and society: but mostly as a reflection on his peers and rivals. Academics that knew Peirce were often influenced heavily by his teachings (these included John Dewey and William James) and were endearing of him and appreciated him openly (Bertrand Russell referring later to Peirce in Principia Mathematica as America's greatest thinker). Others were less than good-natured.

Peirce's significant achievements and abilities could perhaps be said to be nearly matched by another fact of his life: his misfortune at attracting jealous rivals and detractors. These included John Newcomb and Charles William Eliot - who attempted to sabotage his career regularly and thoroughly, and who in both cases succeeded, largely reducing Peirce to ruin in his later life.

Newcomb

Peirce suffered the pain of facial trigeminal neuralgia in his youth, a condition which caused his face to twitch and which, perhaps understandably had the effect on Peirce that "he was, at first, almost stupefied, and then aloof, cold, depressed, extremely suspicious, impatient of the slightest crossing, and subject to violent outbursts of temper". Apart from this, Peirce is not recorded as having been generally suspicious or paranoid. However, had he voiced suspicion that peers and enemies were clandestinely interfering very effectively with his career, he would have been right.

It is thought that personality defects associated with his condition may have later led Peirce into difficulties with the law in New York, where for a time he was wanted for an assault and for outstanding debts (eventually paid for him by family benefactors). However, it is arguable that this was just as much due to - or rather an outcome of - stress resulting from the abuses meted to him by Newcomb and Eliot, whose behavior is a demonstration that academic prowess is no mark of good character, and in Eliot's case that neither is wealth and 'breeding'.

Newcomb was from a poor background and although brilliant in his own right, his accomplishments paled in comparison to those of Peirce. Time spent learning mathematics and logic in Peirce's family home under the tutelage of Peirce's father Benjamin somehow resulted in an abject jealous hatred of Peirce that was long lasting. When it came to Peirce Newcomb's behaviour was cowardly and less than generous, to say the least. Newcomb single handedly clandestinely torpedoed Peirce's career on two separate occasions. He ended Peirce's career at Johns Hopkins by pointing out to a Hopkins trustee that Peirce had co-habitated with his new wife Zina unmarried following his divorce to his first wife. Later in Peirce's life he again single handedly shut down an application Peirce made to the newly formed Carnegie Institute to finance a book comprising his life's work.

Eliot, Unitarian heir of a wealthy Boston banking family, cousin of T.S. Eliot, and a known plutocrat and union hater, took a dislike to Peirce from their first meetings. Eliot multiply stymied an all but secured posting at Harvard by vetoing Peirce's posting to it on several occasions spanning Peirce's entire career. Eliot himself was a comparatively unremarkable chemistry lecturer/professor and ambitious administrator with an interest in educational reform, whose aims were largely centered on influence. He was responsible for significant reforms of Harvard University under his administration - evolving it into a research university - but ealier in his career he failed to secure the position of Rumford Professorship of Chemistry, and he never attained anything remotely close to the academic and intellectual heights familiar to Peirce.

                                                        ========================

In my next article on Peirce, I will discuss in more detail some of his logic and mathematics, and outline some of his semiotic principles. I will also discuss the influence of Peirce's thought on everything from contemporary economics to military thought, and present an analysis of contemporary software development discipline - especially what is called software development lifecycles - in Peircian terms.

  1. Atkin, A. (2004). Charles Sanders Peirce: Pragmatism, IEP URL = <http://www.iep.utm.edu/peircepr/#H6>
  2. Blackburn, Simon. (2004) "Truth: A Guide for the Perplexed", London: Penguin.
  3. Burch, Robert, "Charles Sanders Peirce", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/peirce/>
  4. Brent, Joseph (1998). Charles Sanders Peirce, a life. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press. p. 34. ISBN 0-253-21161-1.
  5. Eisele, Carolyn. (1957) "The Charles S. Peirce-Simon Newcomb Correspondence", Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society Vol. 101, No. 5 , pp. 409-433 Published by: American Philosophical Society URL = <http://www.jstor.org/stable/985195>
  6. Peirce, C.S (1868), "Some Consequences of Four Incapacities", Journal of Speculative Philosophy v. 2, n. 3, pp. 140-57. Reprinted CP 5.264-317, W 2:211-42, EP 1:28-55.Arisbe Eprint
  7. Peirce, C.S. 1998. "The Essential Peirce, the Peirce Edition Project (Vol. 2)", Bloomington IN: Indiana University Press.
  8. Sims, Jeffrey H. (2008) "A fallible groom in the religious thought of C.S. Peirce – a centenary revisitation", Sophia 47 (2):91-105.
POLLS:

Does information exist apart from perceiving agents (without some thinking organism to perceive it)?

Is Philosophy Relevant to Science?